-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 6
/
Copy pathBufferStockTheory-NoAppendix.tex
executable file
·1654 lines (1420 loc) · 118 KB
/
BufferStockTheory-NoAppendix.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
\documentclass[BufferStockTheory]{subfiles}
% WARNING: Different execution depending on whether
% 0. Being compiled as standalone document
% * Compile this file, then main, then this one again
% * Keep iterating until neither file changes
% 0. Being compiled as subfile of main document
% * Just compile main document repeatedly
\input{./econtexRoot}\input{\LaTeXInputs/econtex_onlyinsubfile}
\onlyinsubfile{\externaldocument{\LaTeXInputs/BufferStockTheory}} % Get xrefs -- esp to appendix -- from main file; only works properly if main file has already been compiled;
\begin{document}
% Attempted to make all lines used for Web version contain {Web} (or version with only single curly brace at end) so can be removed with sed
\providecommand{\versn}{pdf} % Version; like, web or pdf or journal submission
\ifthenelse{\boolean{Web}}{ % {Web}
\renewcommand{\versn}{Web} % Too hard to figure out passing -output-directory through make4ht through htlatex, so web version is compiled with junk files in main directory
\renewcommand{\rootFromOut}{.} % {Web}
}{} % {Web}
% Put tiny info header at top to make it easy track git commit that generates it
\hfill{\tiny \jobname~\versn~\today~{at} \DTMcurrenttime, \input{\ResourcesDir/.git-source-commit}~~\input{\ResourcesDir/.git-public-commit}}
\title{Theoretical Foundations of \\ Buffer Stock Saving}
\author{Christopher D. Carroll\authNum}
\keywords{Precautionary saving, buffer stock saving, marginal propensity to consume, permanent income hypothesis, income fluctuation problem}
\jelclass{D81, D91, E21\\
\href{https://econ-ark.org}{\includegraphics{\ResourcesDir/PoweredByEconARK}}
}
\renewcommand{\forcedate}{November 12, 2020}
\date{\forcedate} % Alternative is \date{\today}
\maketitle
\hypertarget{abstract}{}
\begin{abstract}
This paper builds theoretical foundations for rigorous and intuitive understanding of `buffer stock' saving models, pairing each theoretical result with a quantitative illustration. After describing conditions under which a consumption function exists, the paper shows that a `target' buffer stock exists only under strictly stronger conditions. Under these `buffer stock' conditions, the average growth rate of microeconomic consumers' spending matches the average growth rate of their permanent income; conditions required for aggregate `balanced growth' can be looser. Together, the (provided) numerical tools and (proven) analytical results constitute a comprehensive toolkit for understanding buffer stock models.
\end{abstract}
% Various resources
\hypertarget{links}{}
\begin{footnotesize}
\parbox{\textwidth}{
\begin{center}
\begin{tabbing}
\texttt{Dashboard:~} \= \= \texttt{\href{https://econ-ark.org/materials/BufferStockTheory?dashboard}{https://econ-ark.org/materials/BufferStockTheory?dashboard}} \\
\texttt{~~~~~~PDF:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory.pdf}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory.pdf}} \\ % Owner is defined in BST preamble
\texttt{~~~Slides:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory-Slides.pdf}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/BufferStockTheory-Slides.pdf}} \\
\texttt{~~~~~html:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory}} \\
\texttt{~Appendix:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory\#Appendices}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory\#Appendices}} \\
\texttt{~~~bibtex:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/LaTeX/BufferStockTheory-Self.bib}{https://\owner.github.io/BufferStockTheory/LaTeX/BufferStockTheory-Self.bib}} \\
\texttt{~~~GitHub:~} \> \> \texttt{\href{https://github.com/\owner/BufferStockTheory}{https://github.com/\owner/BufferStockTheory}} \\
\end{tabbing}
\end{center}
The \href{https://econ-ark.org/materials/BufferStockTheory?dashboard}{dashboard} will launch a live interactive \href{https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Project\_Jupyter\#Jupyter_Notebook}{Jupyter Notebook} that uses the \href{https://econ-ark/HARK}{Econ-ARK/HARK} toolkit to produce all of the paper's figures (warning: the dashboard may take several minutes to launch).
} % end parbox{\textwidth}
\end{footnotesize}
\begin{authorsinfo}
\name{Contact: \href{mailto:[email protected]}{\texttt{[email protected]}}, Department of Economics, 590 Wyman Hall, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21218, \url{http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll}, and National Bureau of Economic Research.}
\end{authorsinfo}
\newcommand{\thankstext}{All figures and numerical results \href{https://econ-ark.github.io/nbreproduce}{can be automatically reproduced} using the \href{https://econ-ark/HARK}{Econ-ARK/HARK} toolkit, which can be cited per our references (\cite{carroll_et_al-proc-scipy-2018}); for reference to the toolkit itself see \href{https://econ-ark.org/acknowledging/}{Acknowleding Econ-ARK}. Thanks to the \href{https://consumerfinance.gov}{Consumer Financial Protection Bureau} for funding the original creation of the \href{https://econ-ark.org}{Econ-ARK} toolkit; and to the \href{https://sloan.org}{Sloan Foundation} for funding Econ-ARK's \href{https://sloan.org/grant-detail/8071}{extensive further development} that brought it to the point where it could be used for this project. The toolkit can be cited with its digital object identifier, \href{https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.1001067}{10.5281/zenodo.1001067}, as is done in the paper's own references as \cite{carroll_et_al-proc-scipy-2018}.
Thanks to James Feigenbaum, Joseph Kaboski, Miles Kimball, Qingyin Ma, Misuzu Otsuka, Damiano Sandri, John Stachurski, Adam Szeidl, Alexis Akira Toda, Metin Uyanik, Mateo Vel\'asquez-Giraldo, Weifeng Wu, Jiaxiong Yao, and Xudong Zheng for comments on earlier versions of this paper, John Boyd for help in applying his weighted contraction mapping theorem, Ryoji
Hiraguchi for extraordinary mathematical insight that improved the
paper greatly, David Zervos for early guidance to the literature,
and participants in a seminar at Johns Hopkins University and a
presentation at the 2009 meetings of the Society of Economic
Dynamics for their insights.}
\ifthenelse{\boolean{Web}}{}{
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}
\tiny \thankstext
\end{minipage}
} % {Web}
\titlepagefinish
\ifthenelse{\boolean{Web}}{\medskip \noindent {
\begin{minipage}{\textwidth}\baselineskip=0.5 \medskip \tiny \thankstext \medskip \medskip \end{minipage} % {Web}
}}{\pagebreak % {Web}
} % \end{Web}
\hypertarget{Introduction}{}
\section{Introduction}
\label{sec:intro}
In the presence of empirically realistic transitory and permanent shocks to income \textit{a la} \cite{friedmanATheory}, only one more ingredient is required to construct a testable model of optimal consumption: A description of preferences. Modelers usually assume geometric discounting of a constant relative risk aversion utility function, because, starting with Zeldes~\citeyearpar{zeldesStochastic}, a large literature has constructed numerical solutions whose quantitative predictions match microeconomic evidence reasonably well; results are similar whether or not liquidity constraints are imposed.\footnote{For life cycle models without constraints, see \cite{carrollBSLCPIH}; \cite{gpLifeCycle}; for an infinite horizon model without constraints that resembles \cite{deatonLiqConstr}'s constrained model, see \cite{carrollBrookings}.}
A companion theoretical literature has derived analytical properties of limiting ``true'' (nonnumerical) mathematical solutions -- but only for models more complex than the case with just shocks and utility. The extra complexity has been required because standard contraction mapping theorems (beginning with \cite{bellmanDynamicProgramming} and including those building on Stokey et.~al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods}) cannot be applied when the utility function and resources are both unbounded (see \hyperlink{DiffFromLit}{the fuller discussion} at the end of section \ref{subsec:Setup}).
This paper's first technical contribution is to articulate the (loose) conditions under which the simple problem (without shortcuts like a consumption floor or liquidity constraints) defines a contraction mapping with a nondegenerate consumption function. The interesting requirement is a \hyperlink{FVAC}{`Finite Value of Autarky'} condition. The paper's second theoretical contribution is to specify the conditions under which the resulting consumption function implies existence of a `target' wealth-to-permanent-income ratio (the model exhibits `buffer stock' saving behavior). Buffer stock saving arises when the model's parameters satisfy a \hyperlink{GIC}{``Growth Impatience Condition''} that relates preferences and uncertainty to predictable income growth.
\hypertarget{KMP}{}
Even without a formal proof, target saving has been intuitively understood to underlie central quantitative results from the heterogeneous agent macroeconomics literature; for example, the logic of target saving is central to the explanation by \cite{kmpHandbook} of the fact that, during the Great Recession, middle-class consumers cut their consumption more than the poor or the rich. The theory below explains why: Learning that the future has become more uncertain does not change the urgent imperatives of the poor (their high $\uFunc^{\prime}(\cRat)$ means they have little room to maneuver). And, increased labor income uncertainty does not change the behavior of the rich because it poses little risk to their consumption. Only people in the middle have both the motivation and the wiggle-room to reduce their discretionary spending.
Conveniently, elements required for the convergence proof also provide analytical foundations for many other results familiar from the numerical literature. Analytical derivations of these results are provided along the way to the proofs, paired with numerically computed illustrations (made using the open-source \href{https://econ-ark.org}{Econ-ARK} toolkit). The main insights of the paper are instantiated in the toolkit, whose \href{https://hark.readthedocs.io/en/stable/reference/ConsumptionSaving/ConsIndShockModel.html}{buffer stock saving module} flags parametric choices under which a problem fails to define a contraction mapping; a target level of wealth does not exist; or the solution is otherwise surprising.
%Theoretical foundations are valuable both because they provide intuition about the determinants of saving targets, and because they make it easier to develop reliable numerical solution methods (by providing necessary and sufficient restrictions that solutions must satisfy).
The paper proceeds in three parts.
The first part articulates the conditions required for the problem to define a nondegenerate limiting consumption function, and explains how the model relates to those previously considered in the literature. The conditions required for convergence are interestingly parallel to those required for the \hyperlink{Factors-Defined-And-Compared}{liquidity constrained perfect foresight model}; that parallel is explored and explained. Next, the paper derives limiting properties of the consumption function as resources approach infinity, and as they approach their lower bound; then the theorem is proven explaining when the problem defines a contraction mapping. Finally, a related class of commonly-used models (exemplified by Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}) is shown to constitute a particular limit of this paper's model.
The \hyperlink{AnalysisoftheConvergedConsumptionFunction}{next section} examines five key properties of the model. First, as \hyperlink{LimitsAsmtToInfty}{cash approaches infinity} the expected growth rate of consumption and the marginal propensity to consume (MPC) converge to their values in the perfect foresight case. Second, as \hyperlink{LimitsAsmtToZero}{cash approaches zero} the expected growth rate of consumption approaches infinity, and the MPC approaches a simple analytical limit. Third, a theorem explains why, if the consumer is `growth impatient,' a \hyperlink{onetarget}{unique target cash-to-permanent-income ratio} will exist. Fourth, at the target cash ratio, the \hyperlink{cGroLTpGro}{expected growth rate of consumption} is slightly less than the expected growth rate of permanent (noncapital) income. Finally, the expected growth rate of consumption \hyperlink{dcgdxneg}{is declining in the level of cash}. The first four propositions are proven under general assumptions about parameter values; the last is shown to hold if there are no transitory shocks, but may fail in extreme cases if there are both transitory and permanent shocks.
The final section discusses conditions under which, even with a fixed aggregate interest rate that differs from the time preference rate, an economy populated by buffer stock consumers converges to a balanced growth equilibrium in which consumption, income, and wealth all converge to the exogenous growth rate of permanent income (equivalent, here, to productivity). In the terms of \cite{schmitt2003closing}, buffer stock saving is a method of `closing' a small open economy model, and one that is attractive because it requires no controversial assumptions: Not even liquidity constraints.
\hypertarget{The-Problem}{}
\section{The Problem}
\subsection{Setup}
\label{subsec:Setup}
We define the infinite-horizon solution as the limiting first-period solution to a sequence of finite-horizon problems as the horizon becomes arbitrarily large.
That is, fixing a terminal date $T$, we are interested in the final term in the sequence of value functions $\{\vLevBF_{T},\vLevBF_{T-1},...,\vLevBF_{T-n}\}$. We will say that the problem has a `nondegenerate' infinite horizon solution if, corresponding to that value function there is a limiting consumption function $\cFunc = \lim_{n \uparrow \infty} \cFunc_{T-n}$ which is neither zero everywhere nor infinity everywhere (this is fleshed out below).
Concretely, a consumer born $n$ periods before date $T$ solves the problem
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/supfn}
\begin{align*}% \label{eq:supfn}
\vLevBF_{T-n} & = \max~ \Ex_{t}\left[\sum_{i=0}^{n} \DiscFac^{i} \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t+i})\right]
\end{align*}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/supfn}
where
\begin{align}
\uFunc(\bullet)=\bullet^{1-\CRRA}/(1-\CRRA) \label{eq:crrautil}
\end{align}
is a constant relative risk aversion utility function with $\CRRA > 1$.\footnote{The main
results also hold for logarithmic utility which is the limit as
$\CRRA \rightarrow 1$ but incorporating the logarithmic special case
in the proofs is cumbersome and therefore
omitted.} The consumer's initial condition is
defined by market resources $\mLevBF_{t}$ (\cite{deatonLiqConstr}'s
`cash-on-hand') and permanent noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t}$, which
both start out strictly positive, $\{\pLevBF_{t},\mLevBF_{t}\} \in
(0,\infty)$, and the consumer cannot die in debt,
\begin{align}
\cLevBF_{T} & \leq \mLevBF_{T} \label{eq:NoDebtAtDeath}.
\end{align}
In the usual treatment, a dynamic budget constraint (DBC) incorporates
several elements that determine next period's $\mLevBF$ (given this
period's choices); for the detailed analysis here, it will be useful to
disarticulate the steps so that individual ingredients can be separately examined:\hypertarget{DBCParts}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/DBCparts}
\begin{align}
\aLevBF_{t} & = \mLevBF_{t}-\cLevBF_{t} \label{eq:DBCparts} \\
\bLevBF_{t+1} & = \aLevBF_{t} \Rfree \notag \\
\pLevBF_{t+1} & = \pLevBF_{t} \underbrace{\PGro\pShk_{t+1}}_{\equiv \PGro_{t+1}} \notag \\
\mLevBF_{t+1} & = \bLevBF_{t+1} +\pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}, \notag
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/DBCparts} where $\aLevBF_{t}$ indicates the consumer's assets at the end of period $t$, which grow by a fixed interest factor $\Rfree =(1+\rfree)$ between periods, so that $\bLevBF_{t+1}$ is the consumer's financial (`bank') balances before next period's consumption choice;\footnote{Allowing a stochastic interest factor is straightforward but adds little insight for our purposes; however, see \cite{benhabibWealth}, \cite{maTodaRich}, and \cite{mstIncFluct} for the implications of capital income risk for the distribution of wealth and other questions not considered here.} $\mLevBF_{t+1}$ (`market resources') is the sum of financial wealth $\bLevBF_{t+1}$ and noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t+1}\tShkAll_{t+1}$ (permanent noncapital income $\pLevBF_{t+1}$ multiplied by a mean-one iid transitory income shock factor $\tShkAll_{t+1}$; transitory shocks are assumed to satisfy $\Ex_{t}[{\tShkAll}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n\geq 1$). Permanent noncapital income in $t+1$ is equal to its previous value, multiplied by a growth factor $\PGro$, modified by a mean-one iid shock $\pShk_{t+1}$, $\Ex_{t}[{\pShk}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n \geq 1$ satisfying $\pShk \in [\ushort{\pShk},\bar{\pShk}]$ for $0 < \ushort{\pShk} \leq 1 \leq \bar{\pShk} < \infty$ (and $\ushort{\pShk}=\bar{\pShk}=1$ is the degenerate case with no permanent shocks).\footnote{Hereafter for brevity we occasionally drop time subscripts, e.g.\ $\Ex[\pShk^{-\CRRA}]$ signifies $\Ex_{t}[\pShk_{t+1}^{-\CRRA}]$.}
Following~\cite{zeldesStochastic}, in future periods $t+n ~\forall~ n \geq 1$ there is a small probability $\pZero$ that income will be zero (a `zero-income event'),
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/tShkDef}
\begin{equation}
\tShkAll _{t+n}=
\begin{cases}
0\phantom{_{t+1}/\pNotZero} & \text{with probability $\pZero>0$} \\
\tShkEmp_{t+n}/\pNotZero & \text{with probability $\pNotZero $} % \equiv (1-\pZero)
\end{cases} \label{eq:tShkDef}
\end{equation}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/tShkDef}
where $\tShkEmp_{t+n}$ is an iid mean-one random variable
($\Ex_{t}[{\tShkEmp}_{t+n}]=1~\forall~n>0$)
whose distribution satisfies $\tShkEmp \in \lbrack \ushort{\tShkEmp},\bar{\tShkEmp}\rbrack$
where $0<\ushort{\tShkEmp} \leq 1 \leq \bar{\tShkEmp}<\infty$.\footnote{See \cite{rabaultBorrowing} and \cite{lsIncFluct} for analyses of cases where the shock processes have unbounded support.} Call the cumulative
distribution functions $\CDF_{\pShk}$ and $\CDF_{\tShkEmp}$ (where $\CDF_{\tShkAll}$
is derived trivially from \eqref{eq:tShkDef} and $\CDF_{\tShkEmp}$).
\hypertarget{PDV}{}
The model looks more special than it is. In particular, the
assumption of a positive probability of zero-income events may seem
objectionable (though it has empirical support).\footnote{We will calibrate this probability to 0.005 percent to match data from the Panel Study of Income Dynamics (\cite{carrollBrookings}).}
However, it is easy to show that a model with a
nonzero minimum value of $\tShkAll$ (motivated, for example, by the
existence of unemployment insurance) can be redefined by capitalizing
the present discounted value of minimum income into current market assets,\footnote{So long
as unemployment benefits are
proportional to $\pLevBF_{t}$; see the discussion in
section~\ref{sec:discussConvergence}.} transforming
that model back into this one. And no key results would change if the transitory shocks were persistent but mean-reverting, instead of IID.
% Also, the assumption of a positive point mass (as opposed to positive density) for the worst realization of the transitory shock is inessential, but simplifies the proofs and is a powerful aid to intuition.\footnote{}
\hypertarget{DiffFromLit}{} This model differs from Bewley's~\citeyearpar{bewleyPIH} classic formulation in several ways. The CRRA utility function does not satisfy Bewley's assumption that $\uFunc(0)$ is well defined, or that $\uP(0)$ is well defined and finite; indeed, neither the value function nor the marginal value function will be bounded. It differs from Schectman and Escudero~\citeyearpar{seIncFluct} in that they impose liquidity constraints and positive minimum income. It differs from both of these in that it permits permanent growth in income, and also permanent shocks to income, which a large empirical literature finds are quantitatively important in micro data\footnote{MaCurdy~\citeyearpar{macurdyTimeseries}; Abowd and Card~\citeyearpar{acCovariance}; Carroll and Samwick~\citeyearpar{csNature}; Jappelli and Pistaferri~\citeyearpar{jpCins}; Storesletten, Telmer, and Yaron~\citeyearpar{styConsumption}; \cite{blpRisk}} and which since~\cite{friedmanATheory} have been understood to be far more consequential for household welfare than are transitory fluctuations. It differs from Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr} because liquidity constraints are absent; there are separate transitory and permanent shocks ({\it a la} \cite{muthOptimal}); and the transitory shocks here can occasionally cause income to reach zero.\footnote{Below it will become clear that the Deaton model is a particular limit of this paper's model.} It differs from models found in Stokey et.\ al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods} because neither liquidity constraints nor bounds on utility or marginal utility are imposed.\footnote{Similar restrictions to those in the cited literature are made in the well known papers by Scheinkman and Weiss~\citeyearpar{scheinkman&weiss:borrowing}, Clarida~\citeyearpar{claridaErgodic}, and \cite{cwcUnderUncert}. See \cite{tocheUrisk} for an elegant analysis of a related but simpler continuous-time model.}$^{,}$\footnote{\cite{asHomogeneous} relaxed the bounds on the return function, but they address only the deterministic case.} \cite{lsIncFluct} show how to allow unbounded returns by using policy function iteration, but also impose constraints.
The paper with perhaps the most in common with this one is \cite{mstIncFluct}, henceforth MST, who establish the existence and uniqueness of a solution to a general income fluctuation problem in a Markovian setting. The most important differences are that MST impose liquidity constraints, assume that $\uFunc^{\prime}(0)=0$, and assume that for every possible realization of income $Y$, expected marginal utility is finite ($\Ex[\uFunc^{\prime}(Y)]<\infty ~\forall~Y)$. These assumptions are not consistent with the CRRA utility function and income processes used here, whose properties are key to the derivation of the results.\footnote{The incorporation of permanent shocks rules out application of the tools of \cite{mnUnique}, who followed and corrected an error in the fundamental work on the local contraction mapping method developed in \cite{rrExistence}. \cite{mvExistence} provides a correction to \cite{rrExistence}, and provides conditions that are easier to verify, but again only addresses the deterministic case.}
\hypertarget{The-Problem-Can-Be-Rewritten-in-Ratio-Form}{}
\subsection{The Problem Can Be Rewritten in Ratio Form}
\label{subsec:ratio}
We establish a bit more notation by reviewing the standard result that in problems of this class (CRRA utility, permanent shocks) the number of relevant state variables can be reduced from two ($\mLevBF$ and $\pLevBF$) to one $(\mRat = \mLevBF/\pLevBF)$. Generically defining nonbold variables as the boldface counterpart normalized by $\pLevBF_{t}$ (as with $\mRat$), assume that value in the last period of life is $\uFunc(\mLevBF_{T})$, and consider the problem in the second-to-last period,
\begin{align}
\vLevBF_{T-1}(\mLevBF_{T-1},\pLevBF_{T-1}) & =
\max_{\cLevBF_{T-1}}~ \uFunc(\cLevBF_{T-1}) +\DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [ \uFunc(\mLevBF_{T})]
\notag \\
& = \max_{\cRat_{T-1}}~
\uFunc(\pLevBF_{T-1}\cRat_{T-1}) + \DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [\uFunc(\pLevBF_{T}{\mRat}
_{T})] \notag \\
& = \pLevBF_{T-1}^{1-\CRRA}
\left\{\max_{\cRat_{T-1}}~ \uFunc(c_{T-1}) + \DiscFac \Ex_{T-1} [ \uFunc( {\PGro}_{T}
{\mRat}_{T}) ] \right\}, \label{eq:vBold}
\end{align}
where the last line follows because for the CRRA utility function \eqref{eq:crrautil}, $\uFunc(xy) =
x^{1-\CRRA}\uFunc(y)$.
\hypertarget{The-Related-Problem}{}
Now, in a one-time deviation from the notational convention established in the last paragraph, define nonbold `normalized value' not as $\vLevBF_{t}/\pLevBF_{t}$ but as $\vFunc_{t} = \vLevBF_{t}/\pLevBF_{t}^{1-\CRRA}$, because this allows us to exploit features of the related problem,
\begin{align}
\vFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}) & = \max_{\{\cFunc\}_{t}^{T}}~ \uFunc(\cFunc_{t}) +\DiscFac \Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}\vFunc_{t+1}({\mRat}_{t+1})] \notag \\
& \mbox{s.t.} \label{eq:veqn}
\\ {\aRat}_{t} & = \mRat_{t}-c_{t} \notag
\\ {\bRat}_{t+1} & = (\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})\aRat_{t} ~ = ~ \Rnorm_{t+1}\aRat_{t} \notag
\\ \mRat_{t+1} & = \bRat_{t+1}+\tShkAll_{t+1} \notag, %
\end{align}
where $\Rnorm_{t+1}\equiv (\Rfree/\PGro_{t+1})$ is a `growth-normalized' return factor, and the new problem's first order condition is\footnote{Leaving aside their assumptions about the utility function and liquidity constraints, the normalized problem can be viewed as a special case of the model of \cite{mstIncFluct}, with $\Rnorm_{t+1}$ corresponding to their stochastic rate of return on capital and $\DiscFac \PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}$ to their stochastic discount factor, and with the special property that $\Rnorm_{t+1}$ and the modified discount factor are correlated because $\PGro_{t+1}$ plays a role in each.}
\begin{align}
c_{t}^{-\CRRA} & = \Rfree \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[ {\PGro}_{t+1}^{-\CRRA} {\cRat}
_{t+1}^{-\CRRA}]. \label{eq:scaledeuler}
\end{align}
Since $\vFunc_{T}(\mRat_{T}) = \uFunc(\mRat_{T})$, defining $\vFunc_{T-1}(\mRat_{T-1})$ from \eqref{eq:veqn}, we obtain
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{T-1}(\mLevBF_{T-1},\pLevBF_{T-1}) & = \pLevBF_{T-1}^{1-\CRRA} \vFunc_{T-1}(\underbrace{\mLevBF_{T-1}/\pLevBF_{T-1}}_{=\mRat_{T-1}}).
\end{align*}
This logic induces to all earlier periods, so that if we solve the
normalized one-state-variable problem \eqref{eq:veqn}, we
will have solutions to the original problem for any $t<T$
from:
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = \pLevBF_{t}^{1-\CRRA}\vFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}),
\\ \cLevBF_{t}(\mLevBF_{t},\pLevBF_{t}) & = \pLevBF_{t}\cFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}).
\end{align*}
\hypertarget{Definition-of-a-Nondegenerate-Solution}{}
\subsection{Definition of a Nondegenerate Solution}
Formally, we say the problem has a nondegenerate solution if as the horizon $n$ gets arbitrarily large the solution in the first period of life $\cFunc_{T-n}(\mRat)$ defines a unique $\cFunc(\mRat)$:
\begin{align}
\cFunc(\mRat) & \equiv \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \cFunc_{T-n}(\mRat)
\end{align}
that satisfies
\begin{align}
0 & < \cFunc(\mRat) < \infty
\end{align}
for every $0 < \mRat < \infty.$ (`Degenerate' limits will be cases where the limiting consumption function is $\cFunc(\mRat)=0$ or $\cFunc(\mRat)=\infty$.)
\hypertarget{Perfect-Foresight-Benchmarks}{}
\subsection{Perfect Foresight Benchmarks}
The familiar analytical solution to the perfect foresight model, obtained by setting $\pZero=0$ and $\ushort{\tShkEmp}=\bar{\tShkEmp}=\ushort{\pShk}=\bar{\pShk}=1$, allows us to define some remaining notation and terminology.
\hypertarget{Human-Wealth}{}
\subsubsection{Human Wealth}
The dynamic budget constraint, strictly positive marginal utility, and the can't-die-in-debt condition \eqref{eq:NoDebtAtDeath} imply an exactly-holding intertemporal budget constraint (IBC):
\begin{align}
\text{PDV}_{t}(\cLevBF) & = \overbrace{\mLevBF_{t}-\pLevBF_{t}}^{\bLevBF_{t}}+\overbrace{\text{PDV}_{t}(\pLevBF)}^{\hLevBF_{t}}, \label{eq:IBCFinite}
\end{align} \hypertarget{FHWF}{}
where $\bLevBF$ is nonhuman wealth and $\hLevBF_{t}$ is `human wealth,' and with a constant $\Rnorm \equiv \Rfree/\PGro$,
\begin{align}
\hLevBF_{t} & = \pLevBF_{t}+\Rnorm^{-1} \pLevBF_{t} + \Rnorm^{-2} \pLevBF_{t} + ... + \Rnorm^{t-T} \pLevBF_{t} \notag
\\ & = \underbrace{\left(\frac{1-\Rnorm^{-(T-t+1)}}{1-\Rnorm^{-1}}\right)}_{\equiv \hRat_{t}}\pLevBF_{t} \label{eq:HDef}
\end{align}
\hypertarget{FHWC}{}
This equation shows that in order for $\hRat \equiv \lim_{n \rightarrow
\infty} \hRat_{T-n}$ to be finite, we must
impose the Finite Human Wealth Condition (`\FHWC'):
\begin{align}
\underbrace{\PGro/\Rfree}_{\equiv \Rnorm^{-1}} & < 1 \label{eq:FHWC}.
\end{align}
Intuitively, for human wealth to be finite, the growth rate of (noncapital) income must be smaller than
the interest rate at which that income is being discounted.
\hypertarget{Unconstrained-Solution}{}
\hypertarget{PF-Unconstrained-Solution}{}
\subsubsection{PF Unconstrained Solution Exists Under {\RIC} and {\FHWC}} \label{subsec:PFUncon}
\hypertarget{APF}{}
\hypertarget{AIC}{}
The consumption Euler equation holds in every period; with $\uP(\cLevBF)=\cLevBF^{-\CRRA}$, \hypertarget{Pat}{}
\begin{align}
\cLevBF_{t+1}/\cLevBF_{t} & = (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} \equiv \Pat \label{eq:Pat}
\end{align}
where the Old English letter `thorn' represents what we will call the
`Absolute Patience Factor,' or APF:\footnote{Impatience conditions of one kind or
another have figured in intertemporal optimization problems since
such problems were first formalized in economics, most notably by \cite{ramseySave}.
Discussion of these issues has remained central to the literature, and no summary could do justice to the topic; I therefore refrain from even attempting it.}\
\begin{align}
\Pat & = (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} \label{eq:APF}
\end{align}
The sense in which $\Pat$ captures
patience is that if the `absolute impatience condition' (\AIC) holds,
\begin{align}
\label{eq:AIC}
\Pat & < 1,
\end{align}
the consumer will choose to spend an amount too large to sustain indefinitely (the
level of consumption must fall over time). We call such a consumer `absolutely impatient.'\hypertarget{RPF}{}
We next define a `Return Patience Factor' (RPF) that relates absolute patience to the return factor:
\begin{align}
\PatR & \equiv {\Pat}/\Rfree \label{eq:PatR}
\end{align}
and since consumption is growing by $\Pat$ but discounted by $\Rfree$:
\begin{align}
\text{PDV}_{t}(\cLevBF) & = \left(\frac{1-\PatR^{T-t+1}}{1-\PatR}\right)\cLevBF_{t}
\end{align}
from which the IBC \eqref{eq:IBCFinite} implies
\begin{align}
\cLevBF_{t} & = \overbrace{\left(\frac{1-\PatR}{1-\PatR^{T-t+1}}\right)}^{\equiv \MinMPC_{t}}
(\bLevBF_{t}+\hLevBF_{t}) \label{eq:WDef}
\end{align}
which defines a normalized finite-horizon perfect foresight consumption function
\begin{align}
\bar{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat_{T-n}) & = (\overbrace{\mRat_{T-n}-1}^{
\equiv\bRat_{T-n}}+\hRat_{T-n})\MinMPC_{T-n}
\end{align}
where $\MinMPC_{t}$ is the marginal propensity to consume (MPC) because it answers the
question `if the consumer had an extra unit of wealth, how much more would be spent.' \hypertarget{RIC}{}
($\bar{\cFunc}$'s overbar signfies that this function will be an upper bound as we modify the problem to incorporate constraints and uncertainty; analogously, the underbar for $\MPC$ indicates that $\MinMPC$ is a lower bound).
Equation \eqref{eq:WDef} makes plain that for the limiting MPC $\underbar{\MPC}$ to be strictly positive as $n=T-t$ goes to infinity we must impose the Return Impatience Condition (\RIC):
\begin{align}
\PatR & < 1 \label{eq:RIC},
\end{align}
so that
\begin{align}
0 < \MinMPC & \equiv 1-\PatR = \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \MinMPC_{T-n} \label{eq:MinMPCDef}
.
\end{align}
The {\RIC} thus imposes a second kind of `impatience:' The consumer cannot be so pathologically patient as to wish, in the limit as the horizon approaches infinity, to spend nothing today out of an increase in current wealth. That is, the {\RIC} rules out the degenerate limiting solution $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$. We will say that a consumer who satisfies the {\RIC} is `return impatient.'
Given that the {\RIC}~holds, and as before defining limiting objects by the absence of a time subscript (e.g., $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\lim_{n \uparrow \infty} \bar{\cFunc}_{T-n}(\mRat)$), the limiting consumption function will be
\begin{align}\label{eq:cFuncPFUnc}
\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) & = (\mRat+\hRat-1)\MinMPC,
\end{align}
and we now see that in order to rule out the degenerate limiting
solution $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) = \infty$ we need $\hRat$ to be finite; that is, we
must impose the finite human wealth condition \eqref{eq:FHWC}.
\hypertarget{ValuePFAnalytical}{}
Finally, since the perfect foresight
growth factor for consumption is $\Pat$, the fact that $\uFunc(xy) =
x^{1-\CRRA}\uFunc(y)$ allows us to write an analytical expression for value:
\begin{align}
\vRat_{t} & = \uFunc(\cRat_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\cRat_{t}\Pat)+\DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(\cRat_{t} \Pat^{2})+... \label{eq:ValuePFAnalytical}
\\ & = \uFunc(\cRat_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right) \notag
\\ & = \uFunc(\cRat_{t})\left(\frac{1-(\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA})^{T-t+1}}{1-\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA}}\right) \notag
\end{align}
which asymptotes to a finite number as $n=T-t$ approaches $+\infty$ if $\DiscFac \Pat^{1-\CRRA} < 1;$\footnote{This is related to a condition in \cite{asHomogeneous}.} with a bit of algebra,
% \footnote{
% \begin{align*}
% \DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA} & < 1
% \\ \DiscFac (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree\DiscFac & < 1
% \\ (\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} /\Rfree & < 1
% \end{align*}.
% }
this requirement can be shown to be equivalent to the {\RIC}. Thus, the same conditions that guarantee a nondegenerate limiting consumption function also guarantee a nondegenerate limiting value function (which, interestingly, will \textit{not} be true when we incorporate uncertainty).
Conclusions so far are summarized in the first panel of Table~\ref{table:Required}: The PF-Unconstrained model will have a nondegenerate solution if we impose the {\RIC} and {\FHWC}.
\hypertarget{PF-Constrained-Solution}{}
\hypertarget{Constrained-Solution}{}
\subsubsection{PF Constrained Solution Exists Under {\RIC} or Under \{\cncl{\RIC},\PFGIC\}}\label{subsec:PFCon}
If a liquidity constraint requiring $\bRat \geq 0$ is ever to be relevant, it must be
relevant at the lowest possible level of market resources,
$\mRat_{t}=1$, which obtains for a consumer who enters period $t$ with
$\bRat_{t}=0$. The constraint is `relevant' if
it prevents the choice that would otherwise be optimal; at
$\mRat_{t}=1$ the constraint is relevant if the marginal utility from spending all of today's
resources $c_{t}=m_{t}=1$, exceeds the marginal utility from
doing the same thing next period, $\cRat_{t+1}=1$; that is, if such
choices would violate the Euler equation \eqref{eq:scaledeuler}:
\begin{align}
1^{-\CRRA} & > \Rfree \DiscFac (\PGro)^{-\CRRA}1^{-\CRRA} \label{eq:LiqConstrBinds}.
\end{align}
\hypertarget{PFGPF}{}
\hypertarget{PFGIC}{}
By analogy to the return patience factor, we therefore define a `perfect
foresight growth patience factor' (\PFGPF) as
\begin{align}
\PatPGro & = {\Pat}/\PGro, \label{eq:PFGPF}
\end{align}
and define a `perfect foresight growth impatience condition' (\PFGIC)
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PFGIC}
\begin{align}
\PatPGro & < 1 \label{eq:PFGIC}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/PFGIC}
which is equivalent to \eqref{eq:LiqConstrBinds} (exponentiate both
sides by $1/\CRRA$).
\textit{\cncl{\PFGIC} and {\RIC}.} If the {\PFGIC} fails but the \RIC~\eqref{eq:RIC} holds, appendix \ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr} shows that, for some $0 < \mRat_{\#} < 1$, an unconstrained consumer behaving according to
\eqref{eq:cFuncPFUnc} would choose $\cRat < \mRat$ for all $\mRat >
\mRat_{\#}$. In this case the solution to the constrained consumer's problem is simple: For any $\mRat
\geq \mRat_{\#}$ the constraint does not bind (and will never bind in
the future) so here the constrained consumption function is identical
to the unconstrained one. If the consumer were somehow\footnote{``Somehow'' because $\mRat<1$ could only be
obtained by entering the period with $\bRat < 0$ which the constraint
forbids.}
to arrive at an $\mRat < \mRat_{\#} < 1$ the constraint would bind and
the consumer would consume $\cRat=\mRat$. Using the $\constr{\bullet}$ accent to designate version of a function
in the presence of constraints:
\begin{equation}
\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=
\begin{cases}
\mRat & \text{if $\mRat < \mRat_{\#}$} \\
\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat) & \text{if $\mRat \geq \mRat_{\#}$.}
\end{cases}
\end{equation}
\textit{{\PFGIC} and {\RIC}.} More useful is the case where the return impatience and PF growth-impatience conditions both hold. In this case appendix \ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr} shows that the limiting constrained consumption function is piecewise linear, with $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\mRat$ up to a first `kink point' at $\mRat_{\#}^{1}>1$, and with discrete declines in the MPC at a set of kink points $\{\mRat_{\#}^{1},\mRat_{\#}^{2},...\}$. As $\mRat \uparrow \infty$ the constrained consumption function $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ becomes arbitrarily close to the unconstrained $\bar{\cFunc}(\mRat)$, and the marginal propensity to consume function $\constr{\MPCFunc}(\mRat) \equiv \constr{\cFunc}^{\prime}(\mRat)$ limits to $\MinMPC$. Similarly, the value function $\constr{\vFunc}(\mRat)$ is nondegenerate and limits into the value function of the unconstrained consumer. This logic holds even when the finite human wealth condition fails (\cncl{\FHWC}): A solution exists because the constraint prevents the consumer from borrowing against infinite human wealth to finance infinite current consumption. Under these circumstances, the consumer who starts with any amount of resources $\bRat_{t} > 1$ will, over time, run those resources down so that by some finite number of periods $n$ in the future the consumer will reach $\bRat_{t+n} = 0$, and thereafter will set $\cRat = \mRat = 1$ for eternity, a policy that will (using the same steps as for equation \eqref{eq:ValuePFAnalytical}) yield value of \hypertarget{PFFVAC}{} \hypertarget{PFFVAF}{}
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t+n} % & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t+n})\left(1+\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right)
& = \PGro^{n(1-\CRRA)} \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-(\DiscFac
\PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{T-(t+n)+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}}\right),
\end{align*}
which will be finite whenever any of these equivalent conditions holds:
\begin{align}
\overbrace{\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} }^{\equiv \DiscAlt} & < 1 \nonumber
\\ \DiscFac \Rfree \PGro^{-\CRRA} & < \Rfree/\PGro \label{eq:PFFVAC}
\\ \Pat & < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA} \nonumber
\\ \PatPGro & < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}, \nonumber
\end{align}
where we call $\DiscAlt$\footnote{This is another kind of discount factor, so we use the Hebrew `bet' which is a cognate of the Greek `beta'.} the `Perfect Foresight Finite Value Of Autarky Factor' ({\PFVAF}), and \eqref{eq:PFFVAC} is the Perfect Foresight Finite Value of Autarky Condition, \PFFVAC, because it guarantees that a consumer who always spends all permanent income `has finite autarky value.' Note that the last version of the \PFFVAC~in \eqref{eq:PFFVAC} implies the \PFGIC~$\PatPGro < 1$ whenever \cncl{\FHWC} ($\Rfree < \PGro$) holds. So, if \cncl{\FHWC}, value for any finite $\mRat$ will be the sum of two finite numbers: The component due to the unconstrained consumption choice made over the finite horizon leading up to $\bRat_{t+n} = 0$, and the finite component due to the value of consuming all $\pLevBF_{t+n}$ thereafter.
\hypertarget{RICandFHWCFail}{}
\textit{{\PFGIC} and {\cncl{\RIC}}}.
The most peculiar possibility occurs when the \RIC~fails. Under these circumstances the \FHWC~must also fail (Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr}), and the constrained consumption function is nondegenerate. (See appendix Figure~\ref{fig:PFGICHoldsFHWCFailsRICFails} for a numerical example). While it is true that $\lim_{m \uparrow \infty}
\constr{\MPCFunc}(\mRat) = 0$, nevertheless the limiting constrained
consumption function $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)$ is strictly positive
and strictly increasing in $\mRat$. This result interestingly
reconciles the conflicting intuitions from the unconstrained case,
where \cncl{\RIC} would suggest a degenerate limit of
$\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=0$ while \cncl{\FHWC} would suggest a
degenerate limit of $\constr{\cFunc}(\mRat)=\infty$.
\hypertarget{RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVACText}{}
Tables~\ref{table:Comparison} and \ref{table:Required} (and appendix table~\ref{table:LiqConstrScenarios}) codify these points. Perhaps more useful is the intuitive representation of the relations of the conditions for the unconstrained perfect foresight case presented in Figure~\ref{fig:RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVAC}. Each node represents a quantity considered in the foregoing analysis. The arrow associated with each inequality condition reflects the imposition of that condition. For example, one way we wrote the {\PFFVAC} in equation \eqref{eq:PFFVAC} is $\Pat < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA} \PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}$, so imposition of the {\PFFVAC} is captured by the diagonal arrow connecting $\Pat$ and $\Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}$. Traversing the diagram clockwise starting at $\Pat$ involves imposing first the {\PFGIC} then the {\FHWC}, and the consequent arrival at the bottom right node tells us that these two conditions jointly imply that the {\PFFVAC} holds. Reversal of a condition will reverse the arrow's direction; so, for example, the bottommost arrow going from $\Rfree$ to $\Rfree^{1/\CRRA}\PGro^{1-1/\CRRA}$ imposes {\cncl{\FHWC}}; but we can cancel the cancellation and reverse the arrow. This would allow us to traverse the diagram in a clockwise direction from $\Pat$ to $\Rfree$, revealing that imposition of {\PFGIC} and {\FHWC} (and, redundantly, {\FHWC} again) lets us conclude that the {\RIC} holds because the starting point is $\Pat$ and the endpoint is $\Rfree$, and this is a chain of inequalities. (Consult Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxConditionDiagrams} for a detailed exposition of diagrams of this type).
\providecommand{\figName}{RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVAC} % Allows generic definition of hypertargets based on title of figure
\providecommand{\figFile}{\figName} % and on filename
%\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\input{\FigDir/\figName} % Read in the tex to generate the figure
We now turn to the case with uncertainty. The model without constraints but with uncertainty will turn out to be a close parallel to the model with constraints but without uncertainty.
\hypertarget{Uncertainty-Modified-Conditions}{}
\subsection{Uncertainty-Modified Conditions}\label{subsec:UncertaintyModifiedConditions}
\subsubsection{Impatience}
When uncertainty is introduced, the expectation of $\bRat_{t+1}$ can be rewritten as:
\begin{align}
\Ex_{t}[\bRat_{t+1}] & = \aRat_{t}\Ex_{t}[\Rnorm_{t+1}] = \aRat_{t}\Rnorm\Ex_{t}[\pShk_{t+1}^{-1}] \label{eq:EbRat}
\end{align}
where Jensen's inequality guarantees that the expectation of the inverse of the permanent shock is strictly greater than one. It will be convenient to define the object \hypertarget{InvEpShkInv}{}
\begin{align*}
\InvEpShkInv & \equiv (\EpShkInv)^{-1}
\end{align*}
because this permits us to write expressions like the RHS of
\eqref{eq:EbRat} compactly as, e.g., $\aRat_{t}\Rnorm/
\InvEpShkInv^{-1}.$\footnote{One way to think of $\InvEpShkInv$ is as
a particular kind of a `certainty equivalent' of the shock; this
captures the intuition that mean-one shock renders a given mean
level of income less valuable than if the shock did not exist, so
that $\InvEpShkInv < 1$.} We refer to this as the `compensated return,' because it compensates (in a risk-neutral way) for the effect of
uncertainty on the expected growth-normalized return (in the sense implicitly defined in
\eqref{eq:EbRat}).
\hypertarget{GIC}{}
\hypertarget{GICI}{}
\hypertarget{PGroAdj}{}
We can now transparently generalize the \PFGIC~\eqref{eq:PFGIC} by defining a `compensated growth factor' \hypertarget{GPF}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PGroAdj}
\begin{align}
\PGroAdj & = \PGro \InvEpShkInv \label{eq:PGroAdj}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/PGroAdj}
and a compensated Growth Patience Pactor (GPF):
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/PatPGroAdj}
\begin{align}
\PatPGroAdj & = \Pat/\PGroAdj = \Ex[\Pat/\PGro\pShk] \label{eq:GPF}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/PatPGroAdj}
and a straightforward derivation (\eqref{eq:xtp1toinfty} below) yields the conclusion that
\begin{align*}
\lim_{\mRat_{t} \rightarrow \infty} \Ex_{t}[\mRat_{t+1}/\mRat_{t}] & = \PatPGroAdj,
\end{align*}
which implies that if we wish to prevent $\mRat$ from heading to infinity (that is, if we want $m$ to be expected to fall for some large enough value of $m$) we must impose a generalized version of the Perfect Foresight Growth Impatience Condition \eqref{eq:PFGIC}; we call the `Growth Impatience Condition' (\GIC) the requirement that the Growth Patience Factor~\eqref{eq:GPF} must be less than 1:\footnote{Equation \eqref{eq:GIC} is a bit easier to satisfy than the similar condition imposed by Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}: $\left(\Ex[\pShk^{-\CRRA}]\right)^{1/\CRRA} \PatPGro < 1$ to guarantee that his problem defined a contraction mapping.}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/GIC}
\begin{align}
\PatPGroAdj & < 1 \label{eq:GIC}
\end{align}\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/GIC}
which is stronger than the perfect foresight version \eqref{eq:PFGIC} because
\begin{align}
\PGroAdj & < \PGro \label{eq:PGroAdjLTPGro}
\end{align}
(Jensen's inequality implies that $\InvEpShkInv < 1$ for nondegenerate $\pShk$).
\hypertarget{Autarky-Value}{}
\subsubsection{Autarky Value}
Analogously to \eqref{eq:ValuePFAnalytical}, a consumer who spent exactly their permanent income every period would have value determined by the product of the expectation of the (independent) future shocks to permanent income:\hypertarget{uInvEpShkuInv}{}
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t} & = \Ex_{t}\left[\uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}) + \DiscFac \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro_{t+1}) + ... + \DiscFac^{T-t}\uFunc(\pLevBF_{t}\PGro_{t+1}...\PGro_{T})\right] \\
% & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(1+ \DiscFac \Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}] + ... + \DiscFac^{T-t}\Ex_{t}[\PGro_{t+1}^{1-\CRRA}]...\Ex_{t}[\PGro_{T}^{1-\CRRA}]\right) \\
& = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(\frac{1-(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}])^{T-t+1}}{1-\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} \Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}]}\right)
\end{align*}
which invites the definition of a utility-compensated equivalent of the permanent shock,\hypertarget{PGrouAdj}{}
\begin{align*}
\uInvEpShkuInv & = (\Ex[\pShk^{1-\CRRA}])^{1/(1-\CRRA)}
\end{align*}
which will satisfy $\uInvEpShkuInv < 1$ for $\CRRA>1$ and nondegenerate $\pShk$ (and $\uInvEpShkuInv < \InvEpShkInv$ for the reasonable (though not required) case of $\CRRA > 2$);\hypertarget{DiscAltuAdj}{}
defining
\begin{equation}
\label{eq:PGrouAdj}
\PGrouAdj = \PGro \uInvEpShkuInv
\end{equation}
we can see that $\vLevBF_{t}$ will be finite
as $T$ approaches $\infty$ if\hypertarget{FVAC}{}
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/FVAC}
\begin{align}
\overbrace{\DiscFac \PGrouAdj^{1-\CRRA} }^{\equiv \DiscAltuAdj} & < 1 \notag
\\ \DiscFac & < \PGrouAdj^{\CRRA-1} \label{eq:FVAC}
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/FVAC}
which we call the `finite value of autarky' \hypertarget{FVAF}{}
condition (\FVAC) because it guarantees that value is finite for a consumer who always consumes their
(now stochastic) permanent income (and we will call $\DiscAltuAdj$ the `Finite Value of Autarky Factor,' FVAF).\footnote{In a stationary environment -- that is, with $\PGrouAdj=1$ -- this corresponds to an impatience condition imposed by \cite{mstIncFluct}; but their remaining conditions do not correspond to those here, because their problem differs and their method of proof differs.} For nondegenerate $\pShk$, this
condition is stronger
(harder to satisfy in the sense of requiring lower $\DiscFac$) than
the perfect foresight version \eqref{eq:PFFVAC} because $\PGrouAdj <
\PGro$.\footnote{To see this, rewrite \eqref{eq:FVAC} as
\begin{align*}
\DiscFac \Rfree & < \Rfree \PGrouAdj^{\CRRA-1}
\\ (\DiscFac \Rfree)^{1/\CRRA} & < \Rfree^{1/\CRRA} \PGro^{1-1/\CRRA} \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}
\\ \PatPGro & < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA} \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}
\end{align*}
where the last equation is the same as the {\PFFVAC} condition except that the
RHS is multiplied by $\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}$ which is strictly less than 1.}
\begin{comment}
A useful alternative version is
\begin{verbatimwrite}{\EqDir/FVACAlt}
\begin{align}
\DiscFac \Rfree \PGro^{-\CRRA} \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA} & < \Rfree/\PGro \nonumber
\\ \PatPGro \uInvEpShkuInv^{1/\CRRA-1} & < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA} \label{eq:FVACAlt}.
\end{align}
\end{verbatimwrite}
\input{\EqDir/FVACAlt}
\end{comment}
\begin{comment}
In the case where the permanent shocks are lognormally distributed, we have
\begin{align}
\Ex[\pshk^{1-\CRRA}] & = &\exp((1-\CRRA)(-\sigma^{2}_{\pshk}/2)+(1-\CRRA)^{2}\sigma_{\pshk}^{2})
\\ & = \exp((1-\CRRA)((-1/2)+(1-\CRRA))\sigma_{\pshk}^{2})
\\ & = \exp((1-\CRRA)(1/2-\CRRA)\sigma_{\pshk}^{2})
\end{align}
\end{comment}
\begin{comment}
Equation
\eqref{eq:GIC} can be raised to the $\CRRA$ power yielding the
alternative form $(\Rfree \DiscFac) \PGroAdj^{-\CRRA} < 1$ which
Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr} imposed to guarantee that his
problem defined a contraction mapping.
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Baseline-Numerical-Solution}{}
\subsection{The Baseline Numerical Solution}
Figure~\ref{fig:cFuncsConverge}, familiar from the literature, depicts the successive consumption
rules that apply in the last period of life $(\cFunc_{T}(\mRat))$, the
second-to-last period, and earlier periods under baseline parameter values listed in Table~\ref{table:Calibration}. (The 45 degree line is $\cFunc_{T}(\mRat) = m$ because in
the last period of life it is optimal to spend all remaining
resources.)
\hypertarget{Calibration}{}
\input{\TableDir/Parameters}
\hypertarget{Symbols}{}
\input{\TableDir/Calibration}
\providecommand{\figName}{Convergence-of-the-Consumption-Rules} % Allows generic definition of hypertargets based on title of figure
\providecommand{\figFile}{cFuncsConverge} % and on filename
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\input{\FigDir/cFuncsConverge} % Read in the tex to generate the figure
In the figure, the consumption rules appear to converge to a nondegenerate $\cFunc(\mRat)$.
Our next purpose is to show that this appearance is not deceptive.
\hypertarget{Concave-Consumption-Function-Characteristics}{}
\subsection{Concave Consumption Function Characteristics}\label{sec:cExists}
A precondition for the main proof is that the maximization problem \eqref{eq:veqn} defines a sequence of continuously differentiable strictly increasing strictly concave\footnote{With one obvious exception: $\cFunc_{T}(m)$ is linear (and so only weakly concave).} functions $\{\cFunc_{T},\cFunc_{T-1},...\}$. The straightforward but tedious proof is relegated to appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxcExists}. For present purposes, the most important point is that the income process induces what \cite{aiyagari:ge} dubbed a `natural borrowing constraint': $\cFunc_{t}(\mRat) < m$ for all periods $t < T$ because a consumer who spent all available resources would arrive in period $t+1$ with balances $b_{t+1}$ of zero, and then might earn zero income over the remaining horizon, requiring the consumer to spend zero, incurring negative infinite utility. To avoid this disaster, the consumer never spends everything. \cite{zeldesStochastic} seems to have been the first to argue, based on his numerical results, that the natural borrowing constraint was a quantitatively plausible alternative to `artificial' or `ad hoc' borrowing constraints in a life cycle model.\footnote{\cite{carrollBrookings} made the same (numerical) point for infinite horizon models (calibrated to actual empirical data on household income dynamics).}
Strict concavity and continuous differentiability of the consumption function are key elements in many of the arguments below, but are not characteristics of models with `artificial' borrowing constraints. The analytical convenience of these features is considerable, even if models with natural borrowing constraints in practice usually give similar results to those with artificial constraints.
\hypertarget{Bounds-for-the-Consumption-Functions}{}
\subsection{Bounds for the Consumption Functions}
The consumption functions depicted in Figure~\ref{fig:cFuncsConverge} appear
to have limiting slopes as $\mRat \downarrow 0$ and as $\mRat \uparrow
\infty$. This section confirms that impression and derives those
slopes, which also turn out to be useful in the contraction
mapping proof.\footnote{\cite{benhabibWealth} show that the consumption function
becomes linear as wealth approaches infinity in a model with capital income risk and liquidity
constraints; \cite{maTodaRich} show that these results generalize to the limits derived here if capital income is added to the model.}
\newcommand{\NewMaxMinMPC}{\ushort{\MPC}}
Assume that a continuously differentiable concave consumption function exists in period $t+1$, with an origin at
$\cFunc_{t+1}(0)=0$, a minimal MPC $\NewMaxMinMPC_{t+1}>0$, and
maximal MPC $\MaxMPC_{t+1} \leq 1$. (If $t+1 = T$ these will be
$\NewMaxMinMPC_{T}=\MaxMPC_{T}=1$; for earlier periods they will exist
by recursion from the following arguments.)
The MPC bound as wealth approaches infinity is easy to understand: In this case, under our imposed assumption that human wealth is finite, the proportion of consumption that will be financed out of human wealth approaches zero. In consequence, the proportional difference between the solution to the model with uncertainty and the perfect foresight model shrinks to zero. \hypertarget{MPCnvrsLower}{}
In the course of proving this, appendix~\ref{sec:MPCLimits} provides a useful recursive expression (used below) for the (inverse of the) limiting MPC: \hypertarget{WRICCond}{}
\begin{align}
\MinMPC_{t}^{-1} & = 1+\MaxMPS \MinMPC_{t+1}^{-1} \label{eq:MinMPCInv}.
\end{align}
\subsubsection{Weak RIC Conditions}{}\label{sec:WRIC}
\hypertarget{MPCnvrsUpper}{}
\hypertarget{WRIC}{}
There is a parallel expression for the limiting maximal
MPC as $\mRat \downarrow 0$: appendix equation \eqref{eq:MaxMPCInvApndx} shows that, as $\mRat_{t} \uparrow \infty$,
\begin{align}
\MaxMPC_{t}^{-1} & = 1+\MinMPS \MaxMPC_{t+1}^{-1} \label{eq:MaxMPCInv}.
\end{align}
\hypertarget{WRPF}{}
where $\left\{\MaxMPC_{T-n}^{-1}\right\} _{n=0}^{\infty}$ is a decreasing % Correction per MNW 2016-01-30
convergent sequence if the `weak return patience factor' $\pZero^{1/\CRRA}\PatR$ satisfies:
\begin{align}
0 \leq & \pZero^{1/\CRRA} \PatR < 1 \label{eq:WRIC},
\end{align}
a condition that we dub the `Weak Return Impatience Condition' (\WRIC)
because with $\pZero < 1$ it will hold more easily (for a larger set of parameter
values) than the \RIC~($\PatR < 1$).
The essence of the argument is that as wealth approaches zero, the overriding
consideration that limits consumption is the (recursive) fear of the zero-income events. (That is why the probability of the zero
income event $\pZero$ appears in the expression.)
\hypertarget{cBounds}{}
We are now in position to observe that the optimal consumption function must satisfy
\begin{align}
\MinMinMPC_{t} \mRat_{t} ~ \leq & \cFunc_{t}(\mRat_{t}) \leq ~ \MaxMPC_{t} \mRat_{t} \label{eq:cBounds}
\end{align}
because consumption starts at zero and is continuously differentiable (as argued above), is strictly concave (\cite{ckConcavity}), and always exhibits a slope between $\MinMinMPC_{t}$ and $\MaxMPC_{t}$ (the formal proof is provided in appendix \ref{sec:Tcomplete}).
\begin{comment}
If the \FHWC~does not hold, we make do with a less useful bound on the minimal MPC: It is
weakly greater than zero, which follows from the logic in
\ref{sec:cExists}; hence the `max' in \eqref{eq:MinMinMPCDef}.
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Conditions-Under-Which-the-Problem-Defines-a-Contraction-Mapping}{}
\subsection{Conditions Under Which the Problem Defines a Contraction Mapping}
\label{subsec:contraction}
To prove that the consumption rules converge, we need to show that the
problem defines a contraction mapping. As mentioned above, this cannot be proven using the
standard theorems in the literature following Stokey et.\ al.~\citeyearpar{slpMethods},
which require marginal utility to be bounded over the space of
possible values of $\mRat$, because the possibility (however unlikely)
of an unbroken string of zero-income events through the end of the horizon means that marginal utility is unbounded.
Although a recent literature examines the existence and uniqueness
of solutions to Bellman equations in the presence of `unbounded returns' (see, e.g.,
\cite{mnUnique}), the techniques in that literature
cannot be used to solve the problem here because the required conditions
are violated by a problem that incorporates permanent shocks.\footnote{See \cite{yaoNote}
for a detailed discussion of the reasons the existing literature up through \cite{mnUnique} cannot handle
the problem described here.}
Fortunately, Boyd~\citeyearpar{jboydWeighted} provided a weighted contraction mapping theorem that \cite{asHomogeneous} showed could be used to address the homogeneous case (of which CRRA is an example) in a deterministic framework; later, \cite{duranDiscounting} showed how to extend the \cite{jboydWeighted} approach to the stochastic case.
\begin{defn}
Consider any function $\bullet\in \mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ where $\mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ is the space of continuous functions from $\mathscr{A}$ to $%
\mathscr{B}$. Suppose $\phiFunc \in \mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ with $%
\mathscr{B}\subseteq\mathbb{R}$ and $\phiFunc >0$. Then $\bullet$ is $\phiFunc$-bounded if the $\phiFunc$-norm of $\bullet$,
\begin{equation}
\Vert \bullet\Vert _{\phiFunc }=\sup_{\mRat}\left[ \frac{|\bullet(\mRat)|}{\phiFunc (\mRat)}\right] ,
\label{eq:phinorm}
\end{equation}%
is finite.
\end{defn}
For $\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $
defined as the set of functions in
$\mathcal{C}(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B})$ that are $\phiFunc$-bounded;
$\wFunc$, $\xFunc$, $\yFunc$, and $\zFunc$ as examples of
$\phiFunc$-bounded functions; and using {$\mathbf{0}(\mRat)=0$} to
indicate the function that returns zero for any argument,
Boyd~\citeyearpar{jboydWeighted} proves the following.
\textbf{Boyd's Weighted Contraction Mapping Theorem.} \textit{Let $\BoydT:\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right)
\rightarrow \mathcal{C}\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $ such
that}\footnote{We will usually denote the function that results from the mapping as, e.g., $\{\BoydT\wFunc\}$.}$^,$\footnote{To non-theorists, this notation may be slightly confusing; the inequality relations in (1) and (3) are taken to mean `for any specific element $\bullet$ in the domain of the functions in question' so that, e.g., $\xFunc \leq \yFunc$ is short for $\xFunc(\bullet) \leq \yFunc(\bullet)~\forall~\bullet\in \mathscr{A}.$ In this notation, $\zeta \Shrinker \phiFunc$ in (3) is a {\it function} which can be applied to any argument $\bullet$ (because $\phiFunc$ is a function).} \nopagebreak
\begin{align*}
\mbox{(1)} &\BoydT%
\mbox{ {\it is non-decreasing, i.e.\ ${\xFunc} \leq {\yFunc}\Rightarrow
\{\BoydT{\xFunc}\} \leq \{\BoydT{\yFunc}\}$}} \nonumber \\
\mbox{(2)} & \{\BoydT\mathbf{0}\}\in ~ \mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left(\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) \notag \\
\mbox{(3)}
& \mbox{\it There exists some real $0 < \Shrinker < 1$, such that} \\
& \{\BoydT({\wFunc} +\zeta\phiFunc )\} \leq \{\BoydT{\wFunc}\} +\zeta\Shrinker \phiFunc
\mbox{ {\it ~holds for all real $\zeta > 0$} }.
\end{align*}%
\textit{Then $\BoydT$ defines a contraction with a unique fixed point.}
For our problem, take $\mathscr{A}$ as $\mathbb{R}_{>0}$ and $\mathscr{B}$
as $\mathbb{R}$, and define
\begin{align*}
\{\EEndMap \zFunc\}(a_{t}) & = \Ex_{t}\left[\PGro^{1-\CRRA}_{t+1} \zFunc(a_{t} \Rnorm_{t+1} + \tShkAll_{t+1})\right].
\end{align*}
Using this, we introduce the mapping \textit{$\TMap:\mathcal{C}_{\phiFunc }\left( \mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) \rightarrow \mathcal{C}\left(
\mathscr{A},\mathscr{B}\right) $},\footnote{Note that the existence of the maximum is assured by the continuity of $\{\EEndMap \zFunc\}(a_{t})$ (it is continuous because it is the sum of continuous $\phiFunc$-bounded functions $\zFunc$) and the compactness of $[\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]$.}
\begin{comment} %
(In the subtle case when $\MinMinMPC=0$, the compact interval could be revised as $ [(\MinMinMPC+\epsilon) \mRat_{t},
\MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]$ where $\epsilon$ is a very small positive number because obviously $\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}=0$ will not be the $\argmax$)
\end{comment}
\begin{align}
\{\TMap{\zFunc}\}(\mRat_{t}) & = \underset{{\cRat}_{t} \in
[\MinMinMPC \mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]
} \max
\uFunc(c_{t})+\DiscFac \left( \{\EEndMap \zFunc \}(\mRat_{t}-c_{t}) \right) \label{definitionmappingT}.
\end{align}
\begin{comment}
Unpacking the definitions, our mapping $\TMap$ can be written more explicitly as
\begin{align}
\{\TMap\zFunc\}(\mRat_{t}) & = \underset{\cRat_{t} \in [\MinMinMPC
\mRat_{t}, \MaxMPC \mRat_{t}]} \max \left\{
\uFunc(c_{t})+\DiscFac \Ex_{t}\left[ {\PGro}_{t+1} ^{1-\CRRA }\zFunc(
{\aRat}_{t}\Rnorm_{t+1}+\tShkAll_{t+1}) \right] \right\}
.
\end{align}
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{Contraction-Conditions}{}
We can show that our operator $\TMap$ satisfies the conditions that
Boyd requires of his operator $\BoydT$, if we impose two restrictions
on parameter values. The first is the \WRIC~necessary for
convergence of the maximal MPC, equation \eqref{eq:WRIC} above. A
more serious restriction is the utility-compensated Finite Value of
Autarky condition, equation \eqref{eq:FVAC}. (We discuss the
interpretation of these restrictions in detail in section
\ref{sec:discussConvergence} below.) Imposing these restrictions, we
are now in position to state the central theorem of the paper.
\hypertarget{MainTheorem}{}
\setcounter{theorem}{0}
\begin{theorem}
\label{thm:contmap} $\TMap$ is a contraction mapping if
the restrictions on parameter values \eqref{eq:WRIC} and
\eqref{eq:FVAC} are true (that is, if the weak return impatience condition and the finite value of autarky condition hold).
\end{theorem}
Intuitively, Boyd's theorem shows that if you can find a $\phiFunc$ that is everywhere finite but goes to infinity `as fast or faster' than the function you are normalizing with $\phiFunc$, the normalized problem defines a contraction mapping. The intuition for the {\FVAC} condition is just that, with an infinite horizon, with any initial amount of bank balances $\bRat_{0}$, in the limit your value can always be made greater than you would get by consuming exactly the sustainable amount (say, by consuming $(\rfree/\Rfree)\bRat_{0}-\epsilon$ for some small $\epsilon>0$).
The details of the proof are cumbersome, and are therefore relegated to
appendix~\ref{sec:Tcomplete}. Given that the value function
converges, appendix~\ref{subsec:cConverges} shows that the consumption
functions converge.\footnote{MST's proof is for convergence of the consumption policy function directly, rather than of the value function, which is why their conditions are on $\uFunc^{\prime}$, which governs behavior.}
\hypertarget{The-Liquidity-Constrained-Solution-as-a-Limit}{}
\subsection{The Liquidity Constrained Solution as a Limit} \label{sec:deatonIsLimit}
This section explains why a related problem commonly considered in the
literature (e.g., with a simpler income process, by
Deaton~\citeyearpar{deatonLiqConstr}), with a liquidity constraint
and a positive minimum value of income, is the limit of the problem
considered here as the probability $\pZero$ of the zero-income event
approaches zero.
The essence of the argument is easy to state. As noted above, the possibility of earning zero income over the remainder of the horizon prevents the consumer from ending the current period with zero assets because with some finite probability the consumer would be forced to consume zero, which would be infinitely painful.
But the \textit{extent} to which the consumer feels the need to make this
precautionary provision depends on the probability that it will turn
out to matter. As $\pZero \downarrow 0$, that probability becomes
arbitrarily small, so the amount of precautionary saving approaches zero.
But zero precautionary saving is the amount of saving that an impatient liquidity
constrained consumer with perfect foresight would choose.
Another way to understand this is just to think of the liquidity
constraint as being imposed by specifying a component of the utility
function that is zero whenever the consumer ends the period with
(strictly) positive assets, but negative infinity if the consumer
ends the period with (weakly) negative assets.
See appendix \ref{sec:LiqConstrAsLimit} for the formal proof justifying the
foregoing intuitive discussion.
% \hypertarget{Restrained-Consumer}{}
% In the remainder of the paper, in order to avoid a confusion that is common in discussions of models of this type, we will refer to consumers who are solving a problem in which constraints exist, but are not necessarily binding at the moment under consideration, as `restrained' consumers.
\hypertarget{Discussion-of-Parametric-Restrictions}{}
\subsection{Discussion of Parametric Restrictions}\label{sec:discussConvergence}
The full relationship among all the conditions articulated above is represented in Figure~\ref{fig:Inequalities}.
Though the diagram looks complex, it is merely a modified version of \href{fig:RelatePFGICFHWCRICPFFVAC}{the earlier diagram} with further (mostly intermediate) inequalities inserted. Again readers unfamiliar with such diagrams should see Appendix~\ref{sec:ApndxConditionDiagrams}) for a more detailed explanation.
\renewcommand{\figName}{Inequalities} % Allows generic definition of hypertargets based on title of figure
\renewcommand{\figFile}{\figName} % and on filename
\hypertarget{\figFile}{}
\hypertarget{\figName}{}
\input{\FigDir/\figName} % Read in the tex to generate the figure
\begin{comment}
\subsubsection{Perfect Foresight Case}
The unconstrained perfect foresight model is the natural starting
point for developing the intuition behind our parametric restrictions.
As noted above, the Return Impatience Condition (\RIC) is necessary in
this context to guarantee that the PDV of the stream of future
consumption is finite; value is then given by
\begin{align*}
\vLevBF_{t} & = \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\overbrace{(\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}\cLevBF_{t}}^{=\cLevBF_{t+1}})+\DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{2}\cLevBF_{t})+...
\\ & = \uFunc(\cLevBF_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right)
\end{align*}
which has a finite limit so long as $\DiscFac ((\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})^{1-\CRRA} < 1$. But
\begin{align*}
\DiscFac ({\Pat})^{1-\CRRA} & = \DiscFac (\DiscFac \Rfree)^{1/\CRRA - 1}
\\ & = {\Pat}/\Rfree = \PatR
\end{align*}
so the \RIC~guarantees the finiteness of value in addition to the PDV
of consumption (given a finite starting point).
The starting point for consumption is guaranteed to be finite by
imposition of the finite human wealth (\FHWC) requirement. (If human
wealth were unbounded, our unconstrained consumer could freely borrow
in order to spend an infinite amount in every period.)
An alternative way to limit consumption is by imposing a liquidity
constraint $\cRat_{t} \leq \mRat_{t}$. Naturally, in the presence of
such an urgent constraint, other constraints become less important.
Indeed, the strength of the liquidity constraint can be appreciated
from the fact that it prevents consumption from exceeding current
resources even when human wealth is infinite.
Value, in the constrained case, is easy to calculate, because the
constrained consumer's spending is always equal to income, which
always grows by $\PGro$:
\begin{align}
\vLevBF_{t} & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})+\DiscFac \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t} \PGro) + \DiscFac^{2} \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t} \PGro^{2}) ... \notag
\\ & = \uFunc(\pLevBF_{t})\left(1+\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}+(\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA})^{2}+...\right)
\end{align}
which explains the perfect foresight finite value requirement
\eqref{eq:FVAC}: It guarantees that value for the constrained
consumer is finite. Thus, the introduction of constraints is what
makes the finite value requirement interesting; with finite value it becomes
possible to calculate the consequences of alternatives.
\end{comment}
\hypertarget{IntuitionRIC}{}
\subsubsection{Discussion of the \RIC}
In the perfect foresight unconstrained problem
(section~\ref{subsec:PFUncon}), the \RIC~was required for existence of
a nondegenerate solution. It is surprising, therefore, that in the
presence of uncertainty, the \RIC~is neither necessary nor sufficient
for a nondegenerate solution.
\begin{comment}
But if the \RIC~does hold, some useful results can be derived. Arguably
the most fundamental are that the limiting values
for the minimal and maximal marginal propensities to consume implicit in
\eqref{eq:MaxMPCInv} and \eqref{eq:MinMPCInv} are positive and finite.
\end{comment}
We thus begin our discussion by asking what features the problem must
exhibit (given the \FVAC) if the \RIC~fails (that is, $\Rfree < (\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA})$:
\begin{align}
\Rfree & < \overbrace{(\Rfree \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA} ~ < ~ (\Rfree (\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv)^{\CRRA-1})^{1/\CRRA}}^{\text{implied by \FVAC}} \notag
\\ \Rfree & < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}\PGro \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \notag
\\ \Rfree/\PGro & < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \notag
\\ (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1-1/\CRRA} & < \uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA} \label{eq:RICimplies}
\end{align}
but since $\uInvEpShkuInv<1$ and $0 < 1-1/\CRRA < 1$ (because we have
assumed $\CRRA > 1$), this inequality can hold only if $\Rfree/\PGro < 1$; that
is, given the \FVAC, the \RIC~can fail only if human wealth is
unbounded. Unbounded human wealth is permitted here, as in the
perfect foresight liquidity constrained problem. But,
from equation
\eqref{eq:MinMPCInv}, an implication of \cncl{\RIC} is that $\lim_{m
\uparrow \infty} \cFunc^{\prime}(m) = 0$. Thus, interestingly,
the presence of uncertainty both permits unlimited human wealth and at
the same time prevents that unlimited wealth from resulting in
infinite consumption. That is, in the presence of uncertainty,
pathological patience (which in the perfect foresight model with
finite wealth results in consumption of zero) plus infinite human
wealth (which the perfect foresight model prohibits by assumption because it leads
to infinite consumption) combine to yield a unique finite
MPC for any finite value of $\mRat$.\footnote{\cite{maTodaRich} prove that the limiting MPC is zero
in an even more general case where there is also capital income risk.} Note
the close parallel to the conclusion in the perfect foresight
liquidity constrained model in the
\{\PFGIC,\cncl{\RIC}\} case (for detailed analysis of this
case see appendix \ref{sec:ApndxLiqConstr}). There, too, the tension between infinite human wealth
and pathological patience was resolved with a nondegenerate consumption function
whose limiting MPC was zero.
\subsubsection{The \WRIC}
The `weakness' of the additional requirement for contraction, the
weak \RIC, can be seen by asking `under what circumstances
would the \FVAC~hold but the \WRIC~fail?'
Algebraically, the requirement is
\begin{align}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA} & < ~ 1 ~ < (\pZero \DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}/\Rfree^{1-1/\CRRA}. \label{eq:WRICandFVAC}
\end{align}
If there were no conceivable parameter values that could satisfy both
of these inequalities, the \WRIC~would have no force. And if we require $\Rfree \geq 1$, the \WRIC~is indeed
redundant because now $\DiscFac <1<\Rfree^{\CRRA-1}$, so that the \RIC~(and \WRIC) must hold.
But neither theory nor evidence demands that we assume $\Rfree \geq
1$. We can therefore approach the question of the \WRIC's relevance by
asking just how low $\Rfree$ must be for the condition to be relevant.
Suppose for illustration that $\CRRA=2$, $\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-\CRRA}=1.01$,
$\PGro^{1-\CRRA}=1.01^{-1}$ and $\pZero = 0.10$. In that case
\eqref{eq:WRICandFVAC} reduces to
\begin{align*}
\DiscFac & < 1 < (0.1 \DiscFac/\Rfree)^{1/2}
\end{align*}
but since $\DiscFac < 1$ by assumption, the binding requirement is that
\begin{align*}
\Rfree & < \DiscFac/10 \notag
\end{align*}
so that for example if $\DiscFac=0.96$ we would need $\Rfree < 0.096$
(that is, a perpetual riskfree rate of return of worse than -90
percent a year) in order for the \WRIC~to bind.
The relevance of the \WRIC~is indeed ``Weak.''
Perhaps the best way of thinking about this is to note that the space
of parameter values for which the \WRIC~is relevant shrinks out of
existence as $\pZero \rightarrow 0$, which section
\ref{sec:deatonIsLimit} showed was the precise limiting condition
under which behavior becomes arbitrarily close to the liquidity
constrained solution (in the absence of other risks). On the other
hand, when $\pZero = 1$, the consumer has no noncapital income (so
that the \FHWC~holds) and with $\pZero=1$ the \WRIC~is identical to the
RIC; but the \RIC~is
the only condition required for a solution to exist
for a perfect foresight consumer with no noncapital income. Thus the
WRIC~forms a sort of `bridge' between the liquidity constrained and
the unconstrained problems as $\pZero$ moves from 0 to 1.
\hypertarget{The-GIC}{}
\hypertarget{When-the-GIC-Fails}{}
\subsubsection{When the \GIC~Fails}\label{sec:WhenTheGICFails}
If both the \GIC~and the \RIC~hold, the arguments above establish that as $\mRat \uparrow \infty$ the limiting consumption
function asymptotes to the consumption function for the perfect foresight unconstrained function.
The more interesting case is where the \GIC~fails.
\begin{comment}
\WW{}{The same
steps as above lead to the same implication that this requires
$\InvEpShkInv < (\Rfree/\PGro)^{1/\CRRA}\uInvEpShkuInv^{1-1/\CRRA}$,
but when the \RIC~$\Rfree/\PGro > 1$ holds this condition is much more
easily satisfied.}
If the \FVAC~holds but the \GIC~does not, the parameters must satisfy:
\begin{align}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA}\Ex[\pshk^{1-\CRRA}] & < 1 < (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}(\PGro\Ex[\pshk^{-1}])^{-1}. \label{eq:FVACnotGIC}
\end{align}
Note first that by Jensens's inequality $\Ex[\pshk^{1-\CRRA}] > 1$ and $(\Ex[\pshk^{-1}])^{-1} < 1$,
so \eqref{eq:FVACnotGIC} is stronger than
\begin{align}
\DiscFac \PGro^{1-\CRRA} & < 1 < (\Rfree\DiscFac)^{1/\CRRA}/\PGro. \label{eq:PFFVACnotPFGIC}